Drugs In Sports Argumentative Essays

The report in the popular media that some track-and-field athletes have been using a so-called "designer steroid" created to thwart drug testing regimens is the latest installment in the ongoing battle against doping, or the use of performance-enhancing technologies, in sports. Are sports organizations responding appropriately to these challenges, and what is the proper role of physicians in this controversy?

Background

According to the World Anti-Doping Agency, the term "doping" probably comes from the Afrikaans word "dop," a concoction made from grape leaves that Zulu warriors drank before going into battle. In sports, the term was first used to describe the illegal drugging of race horses at the beginning of the 20th century.

Doping in sport now includes a range of practices, including "blood doping" (the practice of autologous or homologous hemoglobin transfusions) and the use of synthetic erythropoeitin (EPO) to increase the number of red blood cells; anabolic steroids and human growth hormone to grow skeletal muscle; stimulants to improve cognitive function and reduce fatigue; and nitrogen tents and "houses" to simulate the effects of sleeping at high altitude. The future holds the promise of more powerful and exotic interventions.

At a recent meeting of the American Society for Gene Therapy, for example, Barry Byrne, Professor of Molecular Genetics and Microbiology at the University of Florida, described a considerable amount of research currently underway to identify biological determinants of athletic performance, including vascular endothelial growth factor (VEGF) to increase vascularization; leptin as a fat metabolizer; myostatin to increase the number of muscle cells; and therapeutic antibodies and cytokines to reduce susceptibility to athletic injuries.

Additional enhancement interventions are expected from the knowledge gained by the Human Genome Project. In July 2003, for example, researchers reported finding that different versions of the alpha-actinin gene were associated with sprinting and endurance running,3 opening the door to genetic testing at an early age to identify promising athletes, and to potential biomedical interventions based on this genetic discovery.

Ethical Principles in Sport

Led by the international Olympic movement, organized sport has attempted to prevent the use of performance-enhancing drugs by banning them, establishing testing programs and punishing athletes caught using prohibited substances. The basic anti-doping principles of sport were laid down in 1967 by the International Olympic Committee:
  1. "protection of the athletes' health";
  2. "respect for medical and sports ethics"; and
  3. "ensuring an equal chance for everyone during competition."
It might seem hard to disagree with the first principle, "protection of athletes' health." Clearly some performance-enhancing drugs are dangerous. Steroids, for example, are associated with a range of side effects, including heart attacks and liver cancer. But sports in general, and some sports in particular, are inherently dangerous. Athletes often injure themselves in training and in a ghoulish fashion. Indeed, for many people, it is the anticipation of beholding injury and even death that makes sports events fun to watch. Think of automobile or downhill ski racing, even football and hockey, not to mention boxing. If athletes are free to accept a certain degree of risk from dangerous sports, why shouldn't they be allowed to accept a comparable, or even greater, risk from enhancements?

Of Risk and Autonomy

An obvious answer is that the fact that some sports are already dangerous does not justify making them more so by allowing the use of dangerous enhancements. But this begs the question of why enhancements should be singled out to ban. Why not require professional boxers to wear enormous protective helmets or to use much more highly cushioned gloves? Why not ban downhill ski racing, extreme sports, tackle football or rigid hockey sticks? The answer is that these actions would alter the fundamental nature of the sports. But that does not explain why we allow these sports to be fundamentally dangerous, or why risks from enhancements are deemed especially unacceptable.

Perhaps the answer lies in the assumption that the use of enhancements violates athletes' autonomy. We might feel less hostile to enhancements, for example, if athletes truly had a choice about whether or not to use them, but we know that, if some athletes use them, they all will have to. Coaches have admitted that athletes must use doping to succeed at highly competitive levels of sport. In short, the objection to the health hazards of enhancements may be that they are not freely chosen.

Yet athletes presumably still have a choice about whether or not to be athletes. Arguably, if you don't want to put up with the risks of enhancements, you can avoid them by becoming a computer nerd or an accountant, just like if you don't want to risk injury from football, you can simply not go out for the team. Why, therefore, focus on enhancements, rather than other risks?

Moreover, athletes routinely lose their autonomy in all sorts of ways. They give up sleep, certain foods, relaxation, recreation and certain relationships to adhere to their rigorous training schedules. Why is the loss of autonomy that characterizes the use of enhancements different from these other sacrifices that may be just as compulsory in order to be competitive?

One argument that is often heard is that the use of enhancements causes a particularly pernicious loss of autonomy because it is ultimately futile. If everyone has to use enhancements to be competitive, enhancement will not offer anyone any advantage. If an enhanced weightlifter can bench-press 50 extra pounds, everyone who uses enhancements will be able to as well, but their relative abilities will stay the same. The use of enhancements will be unavoidable but pointless, like an athletic version of the nuclear arms race. No one will be in any different position from using enhancements than if no one used them. But everyone will have to, and everyone will be exposed to the health hazards.

Equality and Safety

Yet this argument assumes that enhancements affect everyone to the same degree — producing, say, a 50-pound increase in weightlifting ability. But this is not necessarily, or likely, to be the case, since people tend to react somewhat differently to biological interventions. An athlete might hope that by using enhancements he or she would derive a greater advantage than the next person. More importantly, the same criticism made against enhancements can be lodged against all forms of training. Assuming that practicing for hours every day gives all athletes the same degree of improvement, why bother? The athletes would be just as well off if no one practiced, but we don't prohibit practicing, even though it is, in this sense, futile.

The objection to enhancements on the basis of safety might be clearer if enhancements invariably caused serious injury. But some athletes apparently use even potentially dangerous enhancements like steroids and EPO without suffering significant or irreversible harm and some enhancements, like nitrogen tents, seem safe enough to permit widespread use. Moreover, if we are primarily interested in preventing harm, we ought to invest the bulk of our anti-doping money in research to develop safer enhancements, rather than in preventing their use.

This brings us to the third of the IOC's anti-doping principles, "ensuring an equal chance for everyone during competition." As noted above, it may be the case that to remain competitive all athletes have to use enhancements if any do. But what if enhancements were not available to everyone? If they were too costly or the supply were too limited regardless of how much athletes were willing to pay, so that only some athletes were fortunate enough to obtain the performance advantages, the use of enhancements would seem unfair.

On the other hand, athletes are never equal at the moment of competition. They enjoy lots of unfair advantages. Some are born with greater natural abilities. Some have wealthy parents or the good luck not to become injured. Not every Olympic gymnast can be trained by Bela Karoly; not every figure skater is able to grow up practicing on her personal backyard ice rink, like Sara Hughes. It is difficult to understand why sport tolerates these advantages but would not permit the use of enhancements by those who could gain access to them?

One answer is that it is fair to permit people to benefit from the distribution of natural abilities and good fortune because these factors lie outside of our control. But that simply is not true. While we may be unable to control the distribution of talent and luck directly, we certainly can alter their impact. For example, we can make competition more fair by using handicapping to level the uneven playing field created by natural talent and luck. This would increase the role of pure effort and determination as predictors of success, making victory more earned and therefore more deserved. Indeed, we already do this in some sports; there are weight classes in boxing and wrestling, and lead is slipped into the saddles of race horses to offset differences in abilities.

Alternatively, we could use enhancements to increase fairness, by allowing them to be used only by those who were disadvantaged by the natural lottery. For example, enhancements might enable athletes with disabilities to compete in the real rather than in "special" Olympics.

Defending the Ethics of Sports

If the safety and equality objections to performance enhancement are not completely persuasive, we are left with the final IOC principle: the defense of sports ethics. Performance enhancements must be banned because, according to those who make the rules of sport, using them is unethical. Cheating. But why? One reason is that it may allow athletes to avoid putting in the tremendous hard work required to be a successful competitor. Imagine if athletes could infuse a broth of enhancement genes and walk off with Olympic medals without going through the ordeals of practice and conditioning. The medal would seem unearned, the accomplishment inauthentic. In this sense, use of enhancements might be different from natural talents because athletes presumably must train and practice to make use of their talents, and we may be said to be rewarding the work involved rather than just the talent itself.

But hard work is not the only thing we reward. We also reward unearned advantages, like talent or luck. And there is the classic story of the English school testing system for determining whether youngsters should go on to prepare for a university or technical school education. For many years, the story goes, part of the test required the pupils to write an essay on Sir Francis Drake. Since the question was always the same, the students prepared for it in advance, writing drafts and polishing them with the help of their English teachers. The test became little more than an exercise in memorization and penmanship — and, of course, of who had the best English teacher. Then one year, without warning, they changed the question. When the students sat down to take the test, they were asked to write an essay on dogs. One student was not fazed. "There are many different kinds of dogs," he began: "Hounds, sheepdogs, Alsatians, collies, and sea dogs. Sir Francis Drake was a sea dog." The student then proceeded to copy down his essay on Sir Francis Drake.

Your reaction to this story is most likely amusement and admiration for the boy's cleverness. Yet he figured out a way to avoid doing the work the examiners expected of him and all the others. In that sense, he cheated — just as if he had been clever enough to figure out how to get his hands on an enhancement drug and not get caught.

But the story would be different, it might be said, if the student had smuggled a copy of his essay on Sir Francis Drake into the examination room. Why? Because that kind of advantage is against the rules. The IOC's defense of sports ethics might be said to be valid, then, because the use of performance enhancements violates the rules of sport. But that is circular - "enhancement is against the rules because it is against the rules." What is so sacrosanct, after all, about the rules? Rules change all the time. Look at the evolution in the size of tennis racquet heads, for example. Until the 1960s, the poles used for pole vaulting were made out of wood. Then someone began making poles out of fiberglass, which added an additional couple of feet to the maximum height athletes could attain. The rules could have prohibited the use of fiberglass poles, but they didn't, and everyone started using them. You had to in order to remain competitive. Likewise, the rules of sport can be changed, or left unchanged, to accommodate enhancements.

But it would be a mistake to dismiss the significance of rules. It is perfectly appropriate for a sport to make rules and to require competitors to stick to them, to say that you can use fiberglass poles or nitrogen tents, for example, but not steroids or EPO. Moreover, the rules can be completely arbitrary. Indeed, they often are, the reasons for them lost in the mists of their origins. There is nothing inherently wrong with a sport saying that it must be played in a certain arbitrary way, like standing on your head, or without using enhancements.

Playing by the Rules

Rules and the traditions they represent are important because they create a set of expectations among athletes, coaches, judges and spectators. The playing field may not be level, but everyone understands that only certain bumps and dips are permitted. You don't expect to see someone slugged in the face with a cricket bat (although you might with a hockey stick). Moreover, athletes are expected to be role models for young people. The use of enhancements, particularly banned drugs, may be taken as an endorsement of illicit drug use in general.

The consequences of disappointing these public expectations are not to be underestimated. Just look at how upset baseball fans are at reports that home-run hitters use steroids. To preserve spectator loyalty, not to mention revenues, athletic organizations like the International Olympic Committee are perfectly within their rights to make their own rules and enforce them, even if the rules are not always defensible or fair.

Furthermore, it is clearly justifiable for sport to ban dangerous practices. If enhancements are unsafe or their safety uncertain and suspect, it is appropriate to discourage their use in order to protect athletes. Nor is it a contradiction for the rules to permit other dangerous practices. Sport should strive to be as safe as possible, and this justifies not allowing athletes to add to their risk with a new set of dangerous or potentially dangerous behavior, at the same time that the nature of the sport, as defined by the rules, creates inherent dangers. On the other hand, the costs of enforcing a ban may be too high in light of the risk. Testing programs are expensive. Moreover, it is especially difficult to design tests to detect enhancements that are synthetic versions of natural substances found in the body, like EPO, the red blood cell stimulant. Athletes and officials may balk at the intrusiveness of repeated blood or urine testing of questionable validity. This may justify allowing athletes to assume relatively minor risks or those that are commensurate with the risks already inherent in the sport.

Should sport open the door to enhancements that appear to be relatively innocuous? Prohibiting them would be justified if they were not widely available, on the ground that there is no point in adding to the unfairness in sport already created by differences in natural talent, luck or unearned wealth. A ban also can be supported simply on the basis that enhancements violate the rules. But sports organizations should weigh the costs of enforcing the rules against the impact of changing them to permit the use of safe enhancements. A ban against the use of nitrogen tents may be futile, for example, since it may be next to impossible to develop tests to determine if an athlete had done so.

Even in cases where accurate tests could be developed, sport should consider letting the market decide whether relatively safe enhancements should be permitted, especially if they are widely available and the costs of prohibiting them would be substantial. Enough people enjoy watching or participating in power-lifting, an offshoot of weightlifting that does not test competitors for enhancement drugs, that the sport has survived since the early 1960s. On the other hand, XFL football died when people refused to watch it.

The Role of the Physician

The availability of performance enhancements creates special problems for physicians who have athletes as patients. In general, the anti-doping rules of sport are aimed at athletes, teams, and, to a lesser extent, coaches and trainers, and not at physicians who may be the source of the banned substances. While the Anti-Doping Code of the World Anti-Doping Agency prohibits anyone from administering or attempting to administer a banned substance, or assisting, encouraging, aiding, abetting, covering up or being complicit in a violation or attempted violation of an anti-doping rule,1 sports organizations rarely impose penalties on physicians, and then only on team doctors. For example, a Romanian team physician was asked to leave the Olympic Village at the 2000 Sydney Olympics after he gave a banned over-the-counter cold remedy to a gymnast.

Since no drugs have been approved by the FDA to enhance sports performance, physicians who prescribe them to their athlete-patients are engaging in off-label prescribing. With one notable exception — human growth hormone, discussed below — this is not illegal under federal law unless the drug is a controlled substance, such as anabolic steroids or amphetamines. It is a felony to prescribe a controlled substance for other than a legitimate medical purpose and doctors have been prosecuted for prescribing them for use by athletes (e.g., State of Ohio v. Spencer 1998; In re Grand Jury Proceedings 1986).

Human growth hormone, however, is different. In 1991, Congress amended the Federal Food, Drug, and Cosmetic Act to make it a felony to distribute or possess human growth hormone "for any use in humans other than the treatment of disease or other recognized medical condition." Thus, a physician who prescribed human growth hormone for enhancement use by athletes would commit a federal felony even though it is not a controlled substance.

Physicians who prescribe controlled substances to athletes also may be subject to disciplinary action by state medical boards and professional societies. Moreover, physicians in some states may be sanctioned by state medical boards for prescribing certain non-controlled substances. Ohio, for example, prohibits physicians from prescribing, in addition to anabolic steroids, "growth hormones, testosterone or its analogs, human chorionic gonadotropin (HCG) or other hormones for the purpose of enhancing athletic ability."

Confidentiality v. Reporting

What if a physician, other than one employed by a team or sports organization, becomes aware that an adult patient is using banned performance-enhancing drugs in athletic competition? Not only is the physician not required to report the abuse to the sponsoring sports organization, but it is a breach of confidentiality to do so. The only exception would be if the athlete's behavior constituted a serious threat to the health or safety of an identifiable third party.

Although it might be argued that an athlete who uses banned substances jeopardizes the health of competitors by making it necessary for them to do so as well, this is too indirect a threat to health or safety to entitle the physician to breach confidentiality. The physician should make an effort to counsel the patient about the health hazards associated with the use of banned substances. The physician also may terminate the relationship with the patient, provided the patient is given notice and a reasonable opportunity to obtain care elsewhere.

What if the patient using performance-enhancing substances is a minor? May or must the physician notify the parents or guardian? The answer is not clear. The law in most states allows a physician to treat a minor for drug abuse without notifying parents or obtaining their consent, since it is important for minors to feel that they can trust a physician to maintain confidentiality, and this policy encourages them to seek treatment. On the other hand, the physician may not actually be treating the minor for drug abuse, but may learn of the abuse incidentally. Moreover, the physician may feel that the drug use poses a serious threat to the minor's health and wish to notify the parents to enlist their help.

There has been a huge amount of academic, policy, and public debate over the years about doping in sport (i.e. the use of banned performance enhancing substances or drugs and other prohibited practices), and significant resources devoted to addressing it.

Doping is a complex issue – we are still striving to understand how and why it happens, and how to prevent it. But despite the attention doping in sport has received, there is still significant public disagreement about how best to respond to this problem.

Public discussions on doping usually break down - sometimes because of the way we argue about such issues, and often due to inconsistent reasoning. If you want evidence of this take a look at the online comments pages on sports doping articles, or start your own debate with friends and see how far it goes.

Greater clarity is needed on how people think and argue about doping in sport. In this piece I look at the common positions people take on doping, what these commit us to, and the consequences of mixed messages going unchallenged.

Why people dope

Assuming you care about doping in the first place (some people don’t), a key issue to clarify is your theory about why people dope. Your position here is important for discussing the doping issue because, whether you realise it or not, this informs your views on what should be done about it.

Some people believe the doping decision simply comes down to the individual’s desire to win or gain advantages of some type. To them, doping is mostly determined by individual psychological factors, and should therefore be addressed as an issue of personal responsibility and culpability.

Others believe doping choices are driven by a mix of psychological, social, cultural, and systemic factors, rather than individual traits alone. In this view, doping occurs due to the interaction of individual factors (e.g. the desire for winning, improvement, pain management, recovery, career longevity, economic gains, and belonging), and wider socio-cultural and systemic factors (e.g. social background and experiences, team/club/sport culture, sport governance systems, perceived efficacy of anti-doping system, and so on).

Against doping in sport

The question of whether you are for or against doping in sport is also clearly important. If you are against doping in sport, as most people are, there are a number of arguments you might run here.

For example, you may think doping is wrong because:

  • It is against the defined rules and laws governing sport.
  • It is unfair and goes against the level playing field ideal.
  • It represents a health risk and is harmful to the individual.
  • It harms the athletes who choose not to dope (e.g. they exit sport early, or their career is impacted from being cheated out of results and earnings).
  • It contravenes other values defined as the ‘spirit of sport’ (e.g. fair play and honesty; health; character and education; fun and joy; teamwork; respect for self and others; courage; community and solidarity).
  • It sends an unacceptable message about the place and impact of sport in society.

The important thing to note here is that anti-doping advocates vary in their relative emphasis on the above arguments. For some, it is all about the rules of sport, and related ethics and integrity requirements. While for others, the health risk and harm issue is paramount.

For doping in sport

Some people in academic circles argue that doping should be permitted in sport – either in an open free for all as it used to be, under medical supervision, or under the framework of regulated decriminalisation.

The proponents of these more liberal positions on doping commonly argue the following:

  • The level playing field ideal is a myth - there are numerous legal performance enhancing strategies that are unequally available across sports and countries (e.g. expensive training facilities and programs, technologically superior equipment, nutritional, medicinal and other aids etc).
  • Current banned drugs and substances are not inherently harmful, nor the biggest sources of risk and harm when you consider injury rates and long-term physical outcomes in some sport.
  • The true spirit of elite sporting competition is closer to the Athenian ideal of superhuman effort at any cost (including risks and injuries), and doping is consistent with that.
  • Supervised regulated use of performance enhancing drugs and substances, and other banned practices (e.g. blood transfusions) would reduce health risks and harms.
  • Prohibition policies and punitive measures create hidden, uninformed, and riskier doping which exacerbates health and other harms.

Again, people who argue for doping in sport may place different weight on some of the above arguments over others. Further, belief in one or other of these arguments doesn’t commit you to all of them.

Doping prevention approaches

If you are opposed to doping, you should also have a position on how to prevent or reduce it – your discussions on the topic won’t get far if you’re against doping but have nothing to say on what to do about it.

On doping prevention you could take a zero tolerance stance, where you favour restrictive surveillance and testing protocols, and punitive responses for even minor doping transgressions. Implicit in this stance is the belief that because the individual chooses to break known rules by doping, they should take responsibility and be punished accordingly if caught or if they confess, or make later admissions.

Zero tolerance advocates might also believe that doping in sport can ultimately be eradicated. But this is not a necessary belief for this position - for example zero tolerance proponents might simply favour the strong public message in sports doping policy that includes punitive responses.

Alternatively, you could adopt a prevention stance based on harm minimisation principles. Implicit in this position is the belief that doping will always exist in sport, and so the pragmatic aim of prevention is to reduce doping harm (to dopers, other athletes, spectators, sport generally), rather than total eradication of the behaviour.

Harm reduction proponents emphasise an athlete health and welfare focus over harsh punitive measures (i.e. criminalisation specifically). People here are less concerned with upholding individual responsibility as far as punishment goes. They believe doping prevention is better achieved through a focus on broader social, cultural, and systemic factors (e.g. team/club/sport culture, sport governance systems, ethics and integrity culture and systems, etc) rather than individual factors alone.

Punishing dopers doesn’t work

People who argue for harm minimisation approaches believe punitive measures alone will be ineffective in reducing or preventing doping in sport. As above, one reason for this is they believe doping behaviour is driven by a range of factors, and so doping prevention too must take a broad focus (beyond individual behaviour and psychology) to achieve widespread and lasting change.

Another claim made here is that penalties for doping such as fines, suspensions, and even lifetime bans are unlikely to deter doping, and will not eradicate it. The analogy often cited here this is the case of death penalties for murder not halting murder rates, or harsh criminal penalties for illicit drug possession, supply and use failing to reduce or eliminate those proscribed behaviours.

People who are unconvinced about the effect of punitive measures might also point out that even the severest doping penalties are unlikely to work in most cases, because under the current system athletes would challenge such penalties legally to uphold their right to compete, or preserve their rights for future earnings.

Finally, many people against punitive responses to sports doping also place a high value on forgiveness and redemption – a chance to start again with a clean slate. What often comes with this position is the view that the punishment and public humiliations suffered by some dopers (and their families) can be wrongly disproportionate to their original doping offence.

Punitive measures have a place

Supporters of punitive measures do not accept the analogy made between doping and criminal behaviour. They would argue the social, cultural and individual factors (including psychological determinants) of doping in sport are very different to those for murder and illicit drug use. As such, they also claim the thinking behind doping prevention approaches, including the expected impact of severe sanctions (not necessarily criminal), should be different too.

Zero tolerance advocates believe that, if applied appropriately, punitive measures can achieve desired sports doping prevention outcomes (i.e. reduced doping behaviour, reduced harm, or complete eradication). The view here is if doping policy is to include punitive measures (as per the current anti-doping framework), then these should be implemented competently and consistently in accordance with the defined policy aims and processes; and with clear and consistent public messages from sports governing bodies giving unambiguous support.

Supporters of punitive measures might also argue that it is not the current anti-doping policy framework that has failed, but rather the inadequate implementation of this framework by sports governing bodies and systems weakened by inconsistent practices, ineffective leadership, and ambiguous public messages about high profile doping cases.

Middle ground or mixed messages?

Doping in sport debates are often framed around the two ‘sides’ of harm minimisation and zero tolerance. At first glance, such positions appear distinct. In reality, people commonly shift between positions or argue a mix of both.

For example, you might believe that doping requires social determinants focused education and prevention programs (including capacity building in ethics and integrity, athlete culture and health and welfare and so on), AND progressively severe punitive measures in certain circumstances (e.g. for repeat doping offences, systematic team-based doping, related fraud and criminal activity).

A significant challenge for the doping in sport debate is predicting how people will think about and respond to doping cases. Ideally, careful reasoning based on the types of beliefs and positions summarised in this article would lead us to consistent responses, but that is not what often happens.

We see this with the sport of cycling - for example, compare most people’s strident opinions and responses about the Lance Armstrong case, to the relatively muted reactions about other cyclists who have doped (e.g. David Millar, Jan Ullrich, Erik Zabel, George Hincapie, Tyler Hamilton, Stuart O'Grady, Matt White, Neil Stephens, Alberto Contador, Alejandro Valverde, Danilo Di Luca etc).

We also see this in the responses from governments, sports governing bodies, and the sport itself. Again, the official reactions to the above cases in cycling have been markedly different - take a moment to reflect on where each of these riders are currently.

Most sports governing bodies and officials would claim they occupy a middle position between ‘crime and punishment’ and ‘education and prevention’ thinking and approaches. At face value, this seems like a sensible space for doping policy - the best of both worlds. However, this middle space can also be a fertile ground for mixed public messages and inconsistencies on doping that can undermine prevention efforts - as I have argued before in this Column (here and here).

By trying to occupy the middle ground on doping between zero tolerance and harm minimisation - trying to have it both ways - sports governing bodies run the risk of subsequently failing to implement either aspect of their doping prevention policies competently and consistently. Again, take a look at the recent criticisms made about the International Cycling Union.

Doping prevention efforts in all sports are undermined when mixed messages emerge from inconsistent thinking and action around doping policy - and especially when they continue unchallenged in public discussion and debates (e.g. ‘say no to doping’ but ‘say yes to ex-dopers in coaching positions’; ‘our sport is anti-doping’ but ‘ex-dopers manage our pro teams’; ‘strong doping prevention messages are needed’ but ‘ex-dopers are sponsoring elite teams, sports blogs, and working in sports media’).


What does your position on doping in sport commit you to? What should be done to prevent doping? What should we say about the mixed messages that exist about doping in sport?


Further reading: There is of a large academic literature, and a growing research evidence base, underpinning many of the points made in this article. If you are interested in further reading, a reasonable coverage of the issues can be seen at the Wikipedia doping in sport site, and Routledge have published a number of excellent academic books on this topic by some of the leading thinkers in this area.

0 comments

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *